Naturalistic realism etc.
Posted: Thu Nov 30, 2017 12:18 am
Again, I think that we're basically on the same page: Isaac and Korsgaard (and AtheneWins) make what are in some decent sense extraordinary claims, which doesn't have to do with how uncommon they are (thanks for making clear how you're seeing the distinction between extremity and commonality).
Just for example: I think that I really don't know what you mean by 'naturalistic moral realism', but if you mean the Cornell School realism of Boyd and Railton, then I reject it, and I certainly don't think that it's "not hard" to argue in favour of that position which I believe is false. I don't think that ethical claims get their referents in the way that scientifically identified natural kind terms do in any interesting sense, and that it is completely unhelpful to assume that consequentialism is true and then say that the relationship between ethical terms and bringing about the best consequences is the same as that between 'water' and H20. I think that all of the main metaethical options, which are neutral as to the content of normative ethics, are much more plausible: certainly constructivism & expressivist quasi-realism, but even non-naturalism. I myself think that a form of constructivism is the best option: that ethical facts are facts about what we'd find most plausible at the end of ideal philosophical reflection (which we'll never quite actually reach, but can approximate with our actual world philosophical reflection). I am sympathetic to consequentialism but not quite a consequentialist: I certainly believe that there are underrivative reasons of beneficence to promote the well-being of all of those capable of well-being in the literally, morally important sense (which are at least as strong as defended by Singer's weak principle from Famine Affluence and Morality of being required to prevent harm / benefit others at relatively trivial cost to oneself). I used to think but no longer do that reasons of non-maleficence not to inflict harm are stronger than reasons to prevent harm (and yes, I was perfectly willing to say that it was wrong to diver the trolley, but that isn't the view I hold now). The reason I'm not a consequentialist now is that I still think that there are underrivative special obligations that can require you to give up your own greater good for others' somewhat lesser good - e.g. if one has made a promise, they are your child, or you have wronged someone and now have reasons to make amends. So essentially on my view morality is even more demanding than what consequentilaists think: you must level down to the point of marginal well-being to help strangers, but then you might have to give more, because you might have kids, have made promises, or have wronged others. I won't even get into my views about the good, but suffice it to say that I'm not a sum-ranker and I'm not a preference fulfillment theorist about well-being.
That said, you and I probably hold most of the same views about how to treat non-human animals and help the global poor and such. So it's very important that people like you and I can be swayed by and find overlapping consensus on practical ethical arguments, like those made by Singer in Famine Aflluence and Morality and All Animals are Equal - despite our vast differences on metaethics and normative ethics.
I think (and I think it's widely recognized that) it's a really good idea to be as neutral as possible about other philosophical issues in arguing for a specific conclusion so that it can appeal to as wide an audience as possible.brimstoneSalad wrote: ↑Wed Nov 29, 2017 8:47 pm
I don't think they have to be neutral, but if they claim to be and the user of the argument wants to avoid those discussions then they certainly need to be.
I don't think arguments from naturalistic realism are a problem since it's not that hard to argue for that position, and I would say that the strongest arguments are based on that; like arguments from sentience being the trait of moral value, and moral consideration being based on interests.
If you're willing to commit to deliberation leading to naturalistic moral realism, that pretty clearly leads to consequentialism and some kind of preference based framework which necessitates valuing the preferences of sentient beings (as the only ones that have them in any meaningful sense).Margaret Hayek wrote: ↑Wed Nov 29, 2017 7:44 pmand the problem with Isaac (and Korsgaard, and AtheneWins) - unlike those who simply offer good meta-ethically neutral practical ethical arguments like this - is that he (and she, and he) essentially tries to show that substantive ethical claims follow simply from very minimal things like valuing oneself or deliberating.
Just for example: I think that I really don't know what you mean by 'naturalistic moral realism', but if you mean the Cornell School realism of Boyd and Railton, then I reject it, and I certainly don't think that it's "not hard" to argue in favour of that position which I believe is false. I don't think that ethical claims get their referents in the way that scientifically identified natural kind terms do in any interesting sense, and that it is completely unhelpful to assume that consequentialism is true and then say that the relationship between ethical terms and bringing about the best consequences is the same as that between 'water' and H20. I think that all of the main metaethical options, which are neutral as to the content of normative ethics, are much more plausible: certainly constructivism & expressivist quasi-realism, but even non-naturalism. I myself think that a form of constructivism is the best option: that ethical facts are facts about what we'd find most plausible at the end of ideal philosophical reflection (which we'll never quite actually reach, but can approximate with our actual world philosophical reflection). I am sympathetic to consequentialism but not quite a consequentialist: I certainly believe that there are underrivative reasons of beneficence to promote the well-being of all of those capable of well-being in the literally, morally important sense (which are at least as strong as defended by Singer's weak principle from Famine Affluence and Morality of being required to prevent harm / benefit others at relatively trivial cost to oneself). I used to think but no longer do that reasons of non-maleficence not to inflict harm are stronger than reasons to prevent harm (and yes, I was perfectly willing to say that it was wrong to diver the trolley, but that isn't the view I hold now). The reason I'm not a consequentialist now is that I still think that there are underrivative special obligations that can require you to give up your own greater good for others' somewhat lesser good - e.g. if one has made a promise, they are your child, or you have wronged someone and now have reasons to make amends. So essentially on my view morality is even more demanding than what consequentilaists think: you must level down to the point of marginal well-being to help strangers, but then you might have to give more, because you might have kids, have made promises, or have wronged others. I won't even get into my views about the good, but suffice it to say that I'm not a sum-ranker and I'm not a preference fulfillment theorist about well-being.
That said, you and I probably hold most of the same views about how to treat non-human animals and help the global poor and such. So it's very important that people like you and I can be swayed by and find overlapping consensus on practical ethical arguments, like those made by Singer in Famine Aflluence and Morality and All Animals are Equal - despite our vast differences on metaethics and normative ethics.